Chapter 1
Introduction
Referral and conduct of the inquiry
1.1
On 25 June 2015, the Senate referred an inquiry into personal choice and
community impacts to the Senate Economics References Committee (committee) for
inquiry and report by 13 June 2016.[1]
1.2
The committee's terms of reference require it to report on:
The economic and social impact of legislation, policies or
Commonwealth guidelines, with particular reference to:
- the sale and use of tobacco,
tobacco products, nicotine products, and e-cigarettes, including any impact on
the health, enjoyment and finances of users and non-users;
- the sale and service of
alcohol, including any impact on crime and the health, enjoyment and finances
of drinkers and non-drinkers;
- the sale and use of
marijuana and associated products, including any impact on the health, enjoyment
and finances of users and non‑users;
- bicycle helmet laws, including any
impact on the health, enjoyment and finances of cyclists and non-cyclists;
- the classification of
publications, films and computer games; and
- any other measures
introduced to restrict personal choice 'for the individual's own good'.
1.3
In accordance with usual process, the committee advertised the inquiry
on its website and wrote to relevant persons and organisations inviting submissions
to the inquiry.
1.4
To date, the committee has received 485 public submissions and two
confidential submissions. The public submissions are listed at Appendix 1.
1.5
The committee has held seven public hearings. At its first public
hearing, on 11 September 2015 in Canberra, the committee heard evidence on personal
choice and the theoretically underpinnings of the terms of reference. At its second
public hearing, on 3 November 2015, in Parramatta, the committee heard
evidence on proposed restrictions on the activities of fans of the Western
Sydney Wanderers Football Club. At its third public hearing, on 16 November
2015, in Melbourne, the committee heard evidence on mandatory bicycle helmet
laws, and at its fourth public hearing, on 20 November 2015, in Sydney,
the committee heard evidence relating to the sale and service of alcohol, with
particular reference to NSW's 'lockout' laws. A fifth public hearing in Sydney
on 9 March 2016 focused on the sale and use of tobacco, nicotine and
e-cigarettes. The committee's sixth public hearing considered the sale and use
of marijuana on 11 March 2016 in Sydney. At its seventh public hearing on
22 April 2016, in Canberra, the committee heard evidence regarding the
classification of publications, films and computer games.
1.6
This report focuses on the evidence in relation to the first public
hearing. The witnesses who appeared at the first public hearing are listed at
Appendix 2.
1.7
The committee thanks all those who have participated in the inquiry so
far.
Scope of the inquiry
1.8
The committee recognises that support for or opposition to state
intervention in matters of personal choice, or 'paternalism', tends to focus on
particular issues and is not a position derived from first principles. The
committee appreciates that the role of the state in individuals' daily lives
and their decisions is a complex one, as evidenced by the nuanced views of
submitters and witnesses.
1.9
The committee heard conflicting views that state intervention is excessive
in some areas, appropriate in others, and lacking in still others. Given the
spectrum of views, and need to focus on specific matters rather than principled
support or opposition to the role of the state, the committee's intention is to
examine policy areas that have the potential to restrict personal choice and
have elicited strong views from submitters to the inquiry. These policy concerns
are primarily reflected in the inquiry's terms of reference.
1.10
The committee's view is that governance for the good of the public as a
whole is not only necessary, but a key responsibility of government. The
question to be considered is where the line should be drawn when it comes to
state intervention in areas governed by personal choices.
1.11
The committee is also of the view that the role of the state with
regard to children and young people can easily be differentiated from that of
the state with regard to adults. The committee acknowledges legislation that protects
children from harm, and from engaging in unsafe behaviour, should not be
conflated with arguments regarding state intervention in adult decision making.
Protection of children is more appropriately considered in relation to the role
of the state with respect to parents.
1.12
The committee heard that there was generally agreement regarding state intervention
in certain areas of policy.[2]
Mr Christopher Snowdon, Director of Lifestyle Economics, Institute of Economic
Affairs in London, told the committee:
There are genuine public health issues such as clean water,
reducing environmental pollution, road safety laws and vaccinations, where you
cannot as an individual achieve the desired goal without the collective acting
together.[3]
1.13
It was also noted by submitters and witnesses that personal
responsibility was paramount to any discussion of state intervention and
personal choice. Professor Michael Moore, Chief Executive Officer of the Public
Health Association Australia (PHAA), said that 'there should be a balance
between personal responsibility and good government stewardship'.[4]
1.14
Areas such as sanitation, vaccination, product safety and water quality
are examples of these policy areas where it was recognised that the government
has a responsibility to regulate. Therefore, the inquiry does not focus on these
areas, which are regulated for the public benefit and which affect the safety
and wellbeing of all. The committee is of the view that it is the
responsibility of government to regulate these policy areas and that justifications
for government intervention in these areas are more persuasive and less
paternalistic.
1.15
This report focuses on the conceptual aspects of the debate surrounding
paternalism.
Arguments for state intervention in personal choice matters
1.16
At the core of the debate concerning appropriate limits on personal
choice is the question of state intervention, which is often referred to as
'paternalism'.
1.17
The concept of paternalism, as applied to public policy, is the subject
of considerable debate but is generally taken to mean:
...the notion that those in positions of power have, just as in
the relationship between parents and children, the right and the obligation to
overrule the preferences of those deemed incapable of knowing their true
interests.[5]
1.18
Mr Bill New, a public policy researcher, identified three essential
conditions that, in his view, must be met in order for an action to be classed
as paternalistic:
-
there is interference in the self-regarding decision-making
autonomy of one person by another person or by the state;
-
the interference is made in order to further the paternalised
person's interests or welfare; and
-
the interference is made without the past, present or immediately
forthcoming consent of the individual concerned.[6]
1.19
In media commentary on this inquiry, what political philosophers and
legal theorists refer to as 'paternalism' has been widely referred to as 'nanny
statism'.[7]
1.20
The term 'nanny state' has a contested history, as evidenced in
submissions. The PHAA, for example, asserted the following:
It is notable that "Nanny State" is a term that was
coined in 1965 by a British columnist writing in The Spectator...The whole
concept of the "Nanny State" was to point to 'interference' by
governments. It was a term usually used in a pejorative way to discourage
governments from introducing legislation or regulation that might undermine the
power or actions of industry or individuals. It is invariably presented as an
interference with the choices of ordinary people. It is rarely if ever used to
criticise action by governments to protect the community in areas such as
policing and law enforcement, or to opposed public health measures ranging from
safe food and water to quarantine.[8]
1.21
The Institute of Public Affairs pointed out that this is historically in
error:
Opposition to government paternalism wasn't always a conservative
or libertarian thing. Indeed, the use of the word 'nanny' to describe state
interference in individual choices originally came from the left.
In a 1960 article in the New Statesman, the magazine set up
by members of the Fabian Society, nanny was deployed to attack the British
Board of Film Censors. 'Novels and the Press get along, not too calamitously,
without this Nanny; why shouldn't films?' asked a New Statesman columnist
William Whitebait. Nanny 'exercises a crippling drag on the growth of a serious
and healthy British cinema'.
Eight years earlier, the American journalist Dorothy
Thompson...was using nanny to describe British imperialism in the Middle East.
Western empires, Thompson wrote in her syndicated column,
have 'filled the role of headmaster, or Nanny-governess'. The West does not
treat the inhabitants of its colonies as equals. She continued:
It is an amusing notion that comes
to me that, with the retreat of empire, Britons are turning Britain itself into
a Nanny-state, perhaps out of a long habit in persuading or coercing natives to
do what is good for them.[9]
1.22
It is partially true that 'Nanny Statism' and 'Paternalism' are not
perfectly congruent in meaning. However, there is a significant overlap,
particularly when one turns to the concept of 'hard paternalism'.
1.23
Submissions from public health and other organisations put forward
arguments in support of state intervention that centred around:
-
protection: the state has a responsibility to provide
'stewardship';
-
promotion: promoting a healthy and safe population benefits the
economy;
-
correction: state intervention corrects the market failure of
industry dominance; and
-
superior knowledge: the argument that those responsible for
interventions are better qualified to make certain choices than those subject
to intervention.
1.24
The Australian Health Promotion Association (AHPA) submitted that, while
personal choice decision making is important, decisions rarely impact on one
person alone:
The personal freedom to make decisions is an essential requirement
for individual health and wellbeing. However personal freedom is only possible
within supportive environments that protect us from adverse social conditions
and harmful behaviour such as violence and addiction.
Our individual actions do not occur in a vacuum. Invariably
individual actions impact on others within society. Individuals do not always
have all of the required resources at their disposal to weigh up all of the
relevant costs, risks and benefits of decisions in order to make informed decisions.[10]
1.25
The Australian Medical Association (AMA) similarly noted the potential
flow-on effects of personal choices:
Unfortunately, people rarely factor in the consequences of
their behaviour (on themselves and on others) and all too often it is family
members and Governments who are left to provide support and care for poor
individual decision making. More tragically, sometimes innocent victims have to
bear the consequences of poor decision making.[11]
Stewardship
1.26
PHAA submitted that stewardship was a responsibility of government:
Just as parents, schools, professionals and businesses have a
duty of care to the individuals for whom they have responsibility, governments
also have a duty of care to ensure that each of the citizens within the
community have the full opportunity to reach their potential and to ensure they
have the healthiest life.[12]
1.27
According to the World Health Organisation, 'stewardship' refers to the
'careful and responsible management of the well-being of the population' and,
in the most general terms as 'the very essence of good government'.[13]
1.28
A more focused definition was offered by the UK's Nuffield Council of
Bioethics (NCB), which stated:
...the concept of 'stewardship' is intended to convey that
liberal states have a duty to look after important needs of people individually
and collectively. It emphasises the obligation of states to provide conditions
that allow people to be healthy and, in particular, to take measures to reduce
health inequalities.[14]
1.29
The NCB argued that, when it comes to 'stewardship', the 'overall aim
should be to achieve the desired health outcomes while minimising restrictions
on people's freedom'.[15]
1.30
As cited by the PHAA, 'The Nuffield stewardship model suggests a balance
between 'acceptable public health goals' and 'limitations on coercion and
intrusiveness'. Its list of acceptable public health goals include:
- reducing
the risks of ill health that result from other people's actions, such as
drink-driving and smoking in public places;
- reducing
causes of ill health relating to environmental conditions, for instance
provision of clean drinking water and setting housing standards;
- protecting
and promoting the health of children and other vulnerable people;
- helping
people to overcome addictions that are harmful to health or helping them to
avoid unhealthy behaviours;
- ensuring
that it is easy for people to lead a healthy life, for example by providing
convenient and safe opportunities for exercise;
- ensuring
that people have appropriate access to medical services; and,
- reducing
unfair health inequalities.[16]
1.31
At the same time, the Nuffield model says that public health programmes
should:
- not
attempt to coerce adults to lead healthy lives;
- minimise
the use of measures that are implemented without consulting people (either
individually or using democratic procedures); and
- minimise
measures that are very intrusive or conflict with important aspects of personal
life, such as privacy.[17]
Correcting domination by industry/corporations
through state intervention
1.32
Some submissions were concerned with the role of the public sector in
protecting individuals from industry domination, for example through advertising. The committee notes this area
of concern but determined that the matter of industry domination is outside the
scope of the inquiry.
Economic benefits of state
intervention
1.33
The PHAA argued that certain products can generate flow-on costs to the
economy through loss of workforce productivity or expenditure on policing and
the health system. They supported the imposition of taxes in these
circumstances:
Particular products, such as alcohol or tobacco, result in
externalities, which relate to the costs incurred by others beyond those
considered and incurred by individuals in a transaction. Applying taxes is an
efficient and effective way to correct these externalities.[18]
1.34
Similarly, the AMA submitted that there are economic costs attaching to
alcohol and drug misuse which have an impact outside those industries. They put
forward the view that, while these industries contribute to the economy, the
flow-on costs should be considered:
While business and commercial interests are important
considerations, the full extent of harms caused by such products is not borne
by that industry or producer, more often the burden is carried by others (by
the health care system, law enforcement etc).[19]
1.35
The AHPA put the view that health promotion, which helps people avoid
illness, could be of economic benefit, as healthy and active individuals contribute
to workforce productivity and lessen the strain on the healthcare system.[20]
1.36
Nonetheless, it is important that
health promotion be accurately costed. Dr Kesten Green argued in his
submission that the failure to properly calculate economic benefits as well as
costs in public health literature has led to a situation where it has become
difficult to establish 'whether regulation can, and in practice does, improve
outcomes relative to outcomes in the absence of regulation'.[21]
1.37
In policy areas where regulations have been properly costed, Dr Green
went on to note that they have often proven more expensive to implement than
the problem they were meant to solve. In one notorious instance, regulations on
labelling that were intended to encourage people to reduce their calorie
consumption had the opposite effect.[22]
High-stakes or irreversible
decisions
1.38
The committee received evidence that decisions that involve 'high
stakes', where the outcome is largely irreversible, may be instances in which
state intervention is warranted. Political theorist Professor Robert Goodin put
forward the view that paternalism can only be justified for 'big decisions' in
a person's life, particularly big decisions that cannot be reversed.[23]
1.39
For example, the decision to take certain types of drugs or for a
student to drop out of school would be considered a 'big decision', and if that
big decision cannot be reversed because the drug is addictive or the student
cannot re-enrol, then state intervention through paternalistic public policy may
be justified.[24]
1.40
Further, if a big decision could result in the individual's death, there
would, similarly, be a case for paternalism, as there would be no opportunity
for reversal of the decision or the opportunity to learn from the mistake.[25]
In these cases, it may be that the state is acting to protect an individual
from the outcome of a high-stakes or irreversible decision.[26]
1.41
The Australian Drug Foundation also argued that the state has a
responsibility to legislate to protect citizens from taking action or
participating in behaviour that places themselves and others at risk of
preventable harm, particularly when the risk of harm is 'elevated or when the
individual may not fully comprehend the risk entailed'.[27]
1.42
The Australian Psychological Society referred to the role of the state
in promoting 'positive freedom', to compensate those who lack adequate
resources to fully develop knowledge, skills or abilities. The point was also
made in evidence that an overt focus on personal choice or the
conceptualisation of public issues as individual problems risks holding
disadvantaged groups responsible for situations that have 'demonstrable
structural and social causes beyond their control, which could further
marginalise already vulnerable people'.[28]
Short term preferences in decision
making detract from long term interests
1.43
Professor Goodin argued that it is necessary to question an individual's
preferences when he or she makes a decision, and whether they relate to his/her
present or future interests. Other researchers have also considered whether a
person's present interest in an activity is weighted more heavily than his/her
future interest when that person comes to make a decision.[29]
Economists refer to this phenomenon as 'discounting'.
1.44
Professor Julian Le Grand suggested that people may make poor decisions
if their short term interests outweigh their long term interests:
Failures in major long-term decision-making may result from
another problem: that of myopia. Individuals may make wrong decisions about
self‑exclusion, because they are too short-sighted to take proper account
of the future. Myopia is a common phenomenon. Individuals' time horizons are
limited. They do not always consider the long-term; they plan only on the basis
of current events, or on their predictions of the very immediate future. In a
word, they are myopic.[30]
1.45
Professor Goodin gave the example of smoking, noting that it may be an
individual's first order preference to smoke for whatever reason (enjoyment, or
fashion, for example), but their second-order preference will be to stay alive
and healthy.[31]
1.46
In this scenario, the fact that smoking is unhealthy is known to the
smoker, but knowledge and acceptance of this is overridden by their desire, and
the choice, to continue smoking. Professor Goodin argues, however, that:
Say what they may at 16, however, we cannot help supposing
that they will think differently when the pigeons eventually come home to
roost...Insofar as people's preferences are not settled—insofar as they choose
one option now, yet at some later time wish that they had chosen another—we
have another ground for permissible paternalism.[32]
1.47
The policymaker, therefore, has two choices to consider in relation to
the same individual: present and future, noting that the individual in the
future cannot reverse the decisions taken by their 'past' self.
1.48
Significantly, Professor Goodin's position rests on the contention that
paternalism in some areas of public policy is justifiable on the basis of a
person's 'deeper' or second-order preferences, such as their health and general
well-being. Almost by definition, these interests are only disclosed over the
longer term: the consequences of smoking, for instance, can take a number of
decades to develop.
1.49
From Professor Goodin's perspective, paternalistic policies that seek to
improve a person's quality of life, especially over the longer term, are not
only morally justifiable, but politically effective. Smokers who have been
saved from lung cancer are better off, since their deeper interest in their own
health has been realised, while society does not face the burden of dealing
with high rates of smoking-related illnesses. His position comes close to
equating freedom with a person's deeper and longer-term interests – consistent
with Professor Berlin's discussion on 'positive liberty', some of which might
be unknown to persons at earlier stages of their lives.
1.50
In opposition to Professor Goodin's equation of freedom with the
realisation of deeper interests, Professor Isaiah Berlin argued that
paternalistic arguments in favour of securing a person's deeper preferences,
often by restricting their liberty in the present, commit a cardinal error:
they assume that liberty is the equivalent of other social goods, such as
health, happiness or general well-being. While Professor Berlin does not
question the intrinsic importance of these social goods – since health, for
example, is valuable in itself – he is highly resistant to the contention that
good health is the same thing as freedom. In Berlin's judgement:
...everything is what it is: liberty is liberty, not equality
or fairness or justice or culture, or human happiness or a quiet conscience.[33]
1.51
For Professor Berlin, the argument that paternalism can be justified by
realising a person's deeper interests confuses the notion that good health is
desirable with the contention that promoting health is the equivalent of
freedom. Professor Berlin suggests that there is no contradiction in
assuming that a person can be healthier – possibly as a result of paternalistic
public policies – while also being less free. Whether a paternalistic policy is
justifiable is therefore always dependent on the underlying circumstances:
there is no necessary connection between freedom and other valuable social
goods.
Hard and soft paternalism
1.52
Arguments for and against paternalism are nuanced, with submitters and
witnesses drawing a distinction between variants on paternalism, particularly
'soft' and 'hard' paternalism. The Institute of Public Affairs (IPA) submitted
that:
...soft paternalism refers to policy interventions that attempt
to inform consumers about their choices while leaving those choice sets
unchanged. These can include things like labelling requirements or information
campaigns about harmful activity.
Hard paternalism actively constrains choices, by regulating
the circumstance in which a choice may be made, the availability of those
choices, and the legality of the choices. For instance, smoking bans and
bicycle helmet requirements are examples of hard paternalism.[34]
1.53
Similarly, Mr New further set out the distinction between soft and hard
paternalism being contingent on the individual:
The distinction is based on the degree to which the
individual concerned is considered to be acting voluntarily. If someone is
mentally handicapped or mentally ill, under the influence of drugs, or subject
to extreme forms of coercion, then those who support the harm principle will
often submit that interfering in the self-regarding actions of these 'non-voluntary'
individuals is justified on the basis that the decision is not really their
own. The harm is exogenous to the individual. Hard or strong paternalism, on
the other hand, relies on justifying an intervention even though the individual
is in full control of their mental faculties, has good information relating to
the decision to be made, and is not being unduly pressured or coerced in any
way.[35]
1.54
Support or opposition for paternalism in public policy, then, appears to
be along more narrow lines with individuals and organisations submitting that
they supported some, but not other, forms of state intervention. For example,
state intervention was supported on drink driving, but not in relation to
general access to alcohol.
1.55
IPA submitted that '[t]he degree to which a paternalist intervention is
objectionable depends on the degree to which it restrains freedom'.[36]
1.56
Disagreement around paternalism has tended to focus around hard
paternalism, or the intervention of the state in spite of the provision of information
relating to a decision.
Intrusive paternalism or state intervention
1.57
A number of submitters to the inquiry argued that successive governments
had overextended their reach and that individual rights had been restricted.[37]
These submitters emphasised the right of the individual to freedom of choice.
1.58
In his submission to the committee, Professor Philip Pettit argued that
laws enacted in a democracy 'provided a. as required by a constitutional rule
of law, they are the same for all' and 'b. as required by democracy, they are
selected under accepted processes and criteria', don't 'themselves subject us
to a public, alien will' and 'may be required in order to provide effectively
for people's being able to enjoy the conditions necessary for a free,
autonomous life'.[38]
1.59
The IPA submitted their view that:
...individuals should be free to live their lives according to
their values and their preferences. The only activities that can be
legitimately constrained are those which have a direct, material impact on the
rights of others.
This is the perspective which we apply to paternalist public
policy, also known colloquially as 'Nanny State' public policy. These policies
consist of regulatory and taxation interventions aimed at restricting or
influencing individual choices that affect primarily those individuals
themselves.[39]
1.60
Mr Snowdon argued that 'a movement that seeks to regulate a person's
lifestyle for their own good is unethical. It is also damaging to individuals
and therefore to society'. He makes the related point that using high prices to
generate a form of positive liberty in the sense Professor Berlin discusses –
'helping people to follow their true preferences' – has the effect of taking a
'disproportionate share of income from the poor'.[40]
1.61
Commercial Economics Consulting submitted that people require the
ability to make their own decisions about their behaviour in order to feel
empowered and engaged with society. They suggested that there are consequences
to over-regulation:
Over-regulation creates the very real risk that we will
create a society which relies on government as the source of solution for every
problem, whereas, realistically, the way to deal with societies problems is
through the engagement of the citizenry in a communal effort to resolve issues
in the optimal manner possible. Doing so clearly requires the citizenry to be
empowered and for the citizenry to realise that it is the responsibility of
each individual, working together, to resolve issues. That is, to ensure that
personal responsibility is the cornerstone of decision making.[41]
1.62
Some submitters put forward the view that if an individual is entrusted
with the responsibility of voting in an election, that same individual should
be trusted with other decisions regarding their lifestyle.[42]
1.63
The IPA elaborated on this point thus:
Paternalism violates one of the core ethical constructs at
the heart of our liberal democracy: the claim that we are each capable of
exercising rational and self-regarding decision making, and have the right to
make such decisions at the ballot box. If we believe that claim holds true for
voting, why do we not believe it holds true for market choice?
It is important that policymakers understand the full significance
of their assertion that individuals are unable to make decisions on their own
behalf, and that they require the assistance of higher authorities.[43]
1.64
Mr Abe Salt suggested that the application of government intervention
was inconsistent, with some products banned while others taxed, an unfortunate
example of policy inconsistency and discretion, criticised with considerable
force by Professor Pettit in his scholarship on the exercise of arbitrary
power. Mr Salt offered an example of tobacco products: cigarettes are taxed
while e-cigarettes are banned.[44]
1.65
The committee received hundreds of submissions arguing for and against
state intervention in various matters of personal choice. This inquiry will
explore the issues raised in a number of areas where it is argued that
individual freedom to make decisions is being undermined by paternalistic state
overreach.
Senator Chris Ketter
Committee Chair
Navigation: Previous Page | Contents | Next Page