Compliance with Australia's international obligations
Human Rights
Obligations
3.1
Australia has voluntarily accepted obligations under the seven core
United Nations (UN) human rights treaties. It is a general principle of
international human rights law that the rights protected by the human rights
treaties are to be interpreted generously and any limitations on human rights
are to be interpreted narrowly.
3.2
International human rights law recognises that limits may be placed on
most rights and freedoms—there are few absolute rights (that is, rights which
cannot be limited in any circumstances).[1]
All other rights may be limited as long as the limitation meets certain
standards. In general, any measure that limits a human right must comply with
the following criteria (the limitation criteria):
-
be prescribed by law;
-
be in pursuit of a legitimate objective;
-
be rationally connected to its stated objective; and
-
be a proportionate way to achieve that objective.[2]
3.3
Australian human rights commitments are protections that apply to all
individuals. These protections include the Right to freedom of thought,
conscience and religion and the Right to non-discrimination and equality
before the law. The committee heard substantial evidence, from both sides
of the debate on same-sex marriage, on where the line between competing rights
should be drawn. International law does set out in considerable detail, as
developed later in this chapter, how rights are to be preserved when they come
into conflict.
Human Rights engaged by the marriage debate
3.4
Australia is the signatory to several international instruments on human
rights relating to marriage and familial relationships, some of which have been
ratified. The human rights framework does not have a single explicit
human rights instrument for gender identity and sexuality, nor an express right
to same-sex marriage. However, all Australians enjoy the human rights set out
in the instruments.
3.5
Australia is the signatory to several international instruments on human
rights relating to marriage and familial relationships, some of which have been
ratified
-
Internationally, the right to marry is enshrined in Article 23 of
the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR).
-
The right to non-discrimination and equality is enshrined in the Articles
2 and 26 of the ICCPR.
-
Freedom of religion, including the freedom to publically manifest
one’s religious beliefs is enshrined in Article 18(1) of the ICCPR, described
as 'freedom, either individually or in community with others and in public or
private, to manifest his religion or belief in worship, observance, practice
and teaching.'
International jurisprudence on the introduction of same-sex marriage
3.6
The UN Human Rights Committee (UN HRC) has only considered the issue of
same-sex marriage once, in the case of Joslin v New Zealand (Joslin) in
1999. The UN HRC found that:
In light of the scope of the right to marry under article 23,
paragraph 2, of the Covenant, the Committee cannot find that by mere
refusal to provide for marriage between homosexual couples, the State party has
violated the rights of the authors under articles 16, 17, 23, paragraphs 1 and
2, or 26 of the Covenant.[3]
3.7
In recent cases, the European Court of Human Rights (ECHR) has similarly
concluded that a comparative provision in the European Convention on Human
Rights does not require Contracting States to afford access to same-sex
marriage. In the 2014 case, Hämäläinen v Finland, the ECHR ruled that
Article 12 and Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights:
[Did] not impose an obligation on
Contracting States to grant same-sex couples access to marriage. Nor could
Article 8, a provision of more general purpose and scope, be interpreted as
imposing such an obligation.[4]
3.8
Despite these rulings, the ECHR has recognised that this is an evolving
question,[5]
and in recent cases has moved towards encouraging states to offer protection in
law to same-sex couples that is equivalent to marriage. In the 2013 case Vallianatos and others v Greece, the Grand
Chamber of the ECHR held:
[I]t was discriminatory for Greek law to limit civil unions
to heterosexual couples. The Grand Chamber did not declare a conventional right
to legal recognition of same-sex partnerships. However, the Court called on
European legislators, when legislating on family, to choose measures that 'take
into account developments in society... including the fact that there is not just
one way or one choice when it comes to leading one's family or private life'.[6]
3.9
A further affirmation of this position was the 2015 case of Oliari
and Others v Italy, where the ECHR identified the relevant criteria for
determining claims of equality as:
...the extent to which same-sex couples are 'in a relevantly
similar situation to a different-sex couple as regards their need for legal
recognition and protection of their relationship'.[7]
3.10
Some commentators have argued that the ECHR is moving towards
recognising a right for legal recognition of same-sex relationships, and
possibly even same-sex marriage.[8]
As set out further below, other commentators have contested these claims.
Right to marry
3.11
As noted in chapter two, a number of submitters and witnesses supported
the proposed new definition of 'marriage', with some arguing that the amended
definition would be consistent with Article 23 of the International Covenant
on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR).[9]
3.12
Article 23 of the ICCPR protects 'the right of men and women of
marriageable age to marry and to found a family'.[10]
In 1999, the UN HRC considered whether this right encompasses same-sex marriage,
ultimately finding that it does not. Further, a State Party is not obliged by
Article 23 of the ICCPR to introduce same-sex marriage.[11]
3.13
The Joslin decision has been criticised extensively by some international
human rights law scholars and theorists. For example, Professor Gerber and
others have argued that the decision is no longer good law.[12]
3.14
Several submitters and witnesses argued that the authoritative case—Joslin
v New Zealand—means that the proposed new definition of 'marriage' is not
consistent with the right to marry. Professor Patrick Parkinson submitted:
People often make claims about human rights to support
whatever policy position they hold; it has become part of the rhetoric of
advocacy. But there is no international human rights treaty to which Australia
is a signatory or indeed to which it is not a signatory, which declares an
international human right for same-sex couples to marry. Unsurprisingly, given
its age, the only specific international convention on marriage, the Convention
on Consent to Marriage, Minimum Age for Marriage and Registration of Marriages
(1962) assumes that marriage is a heterosexual union.[13]
3.15
In the Joslin case, the UN HRC determined under Article 23(2) that the
right to marry under the ICCPR is confined to a right of opposite-sex couples
to marry due to the interpretation that the terms 'men and women' restricted
marriage, by definition, to opposite sex couples. Given this definitional
construct, the refusal to provide for same-sex marriage does not breach the
right to equality and non-discrimination.[14]
3.16
Queensland lawyer Mark Fowler supported the position of the UN HRC in
the Joslin case as reflective of the intention of the ICCPR:
[T]hey referred to the definition of marriage under the
international covenant as being the sole reference to persons that was gender
specific. Every other reference is to 'people' or to 'persons' and so on. They
thought that was very informative in terms of the intention of the covenant.[15]
3.17
The Institute for Civil Society agreed with Mark Fowler that the Joslin
judgement, and the many judgements of the ECHR, evidence that there is no human
right to same sex marriage:
There is no international human right to same sex marriage.
As Mark Fowler has demonstrated in his submission to this inquiry both the UN
Human Rights Committee in Joslin v New Zealand interpreting the ICCPR
and the European Court of Human Rights in its decisions on the European
Covenant on Human Rights establish that a state is not obliged by the equality
rights in those instruments to introduce same sex marriage.[16]
3.18
The Castan Centre for Human Rights concurred that, as things currently
stand, there is no right to same sex marriage under Article 23 of the ICCPR.[17]
The impact of developments since
the Joslin case
3.19
However, submitters posed a number of questions around the contemporary relevance,
and the narrow scope of the Joslin decision. The length of time since the
judgement is a feature of some submitters' arguments that it does not hold the
authority or relevance today that it may have done at the time of the ruling. Those
submitters suggested that the recognition of same-sex marriage in a number of
jurisdictions may influence the findings of the UN HRC if the case were heard
today. For example, the Law Council of Australia considered:
The increased number of States that recognise same-sex
marriages in the nearly two decades since the Joslin case was decided, together
with jurisprudence concerning the significance of the principles of equality
and non-discrimination may suggest that the approach of the UNHRC in that case
may no longer be followed.[18]
3.20
Amnesty International put to the committee:
...it would be very unusual...that the Human Rights Committee put
forward a judgement that is so out of step at the time with the number of
countries that actually recognise this right. That has completely changed now.
The case that you talked about was a New Zealand case. Even New Zealand now has
legalised marriage equality.[19]
3.21
Mark Fowler took a different view, submitting:
Joslin’s case was decided seventeen years ago. In their study
of the average age of judicial authorities cited by courts of appeal in an
American context, Landes and Posner found that the unweighted average age to be
18.5 years, and the weighted average age to be 19.1 years. That is, half of the
precedents cited were dated prior to those timeframes.... The proposition that an
authority of seventeen years of age can be ignored as ‘a long time ago’ is not
supportable. This is even more so the case in the context of a jurisdiction
where no subsequent authority has issued.[20]
3.22
Amnesty International’s view was supported by the LGBTI Legal Service
however:
At that time only one country, the Netherlands, had legalised
same-sex marriage. Since that time there have been over 20. As with any court,
the judgements progress as social values change. I would submit that now,
considering the further cases that have followed Joslin, we are heading in a
direction where the right to equality and non-discrimination does cover
marriage equality.[21]
3.23
The Human Rights Law Centre (HRLC) cited the fact that New Zealand had
since introduced same-sex marriage as proof that whilst the Joslin decision did
not 'impose a positive obligation on states to legislate for marriage
equality', it certainly 'does not prevent countries from recognising same-sex
marriage'.[22]
3.24
In support of this argument, some submitters and witnesses noted the
European decision in Schalk and Kopf v Austria, where the ECHR decided
that 'it would no longer consider that the right to marry...must in all
circumstances be limited to marriage between two persons of the opposite sex'.[23]
3.25
Other witnesses took a contrary view, for example Mark Fowler stated:
The
reason reliance upon Schalk and Kopf is misplaced is that in that case,
the basis for the ECHR’s finding ... was the provisions of the Charter of
Fundamental Rights of the European Union 2000. The provision concerning
marriage in that Charter (Article 9) does not contain gender specific
references, as does the equivalent Article (Article 12) in the European
Convention on Human Rights. Although the European Union Charter establishes a
completely distinct jurisdiction, is not binding on States Parties to the
Convention, and has a distinct State membership, the ECHR saw fit to reference
the Charter in interpreting the Convention. The Court was divided over the
issue, with the decision only narrowly passing on a 4-3 majority...[24]
Australia
being subject to the ICCPR, is not subject to any subsequent definition of
marriage that removes the reference to men and women. The recasting of the
definition in a subsequent Charter was the reason for the conclusion of the
ECHR that marriage no longer is to be considered to be between a man and a
woman. Such does not apply to parties to the ICCPR.[25]
3.26
Professor Parkinson and the Wilberforce Foundation also questioned the
logic of a UN HRC decision losing authority due to 'evolving state practice.
Noting the vastly greater number of nations which have laws allowing polygamous
marriage, Professor Parkinson stated':
[I]f State practices are to be the guide to the
interpretation of international human rights law, then there must be a human
right to marry polygamously.[26]
3.27
The Wilberforce Foundation suggested:
If the popular contemporary view of marriage in Australia is no
longer the traditional or conjugal view the first step for any government
considering reform ought be to first consider what marriage is now intended to
mean. Without this understanding the reasons for any continued involvement of
the State in marriage remain unclear. [27]
3.28
In relation to the interpretive principle that allows reference to
evolving State practice in international law, Mark Fowler stated that the View
of the UN Human Rights Committee in Roger Judge v Canada, a matter
concerning the death penalty, does not support the contention that the
‘broadening international consensus’ applies in this context:
Australia is subject to the ICCPR. As at the current date, 21
of 169 State Parties to the ICCPR have redefined marriage. This represents 12%
of the total of State Parties... recognition of same-sex marriage cannot be
considered to be representative of an evolving practice. This is supported by
the fact that the ECHR has not redefined marriage on the basis of the broadening
consensus doctrine, even where higher levels of adoption of same sex marriage
have been evidenced than that amongst ICCPR State Parties.[28]
Different, but still equal?
3.29
The question of whether different treatment under the law always amounts
to discrimination has arisen in international jurisprudence on the issue of
same sex marriage. The UN HCR General Comment 18 on Article 26 of the ICCPR is
clear that under certain circumstances it does not:
[T]he Committee observes that not every differentiation of
treatment will constitute discrimination, if the criteria for such
differentiation are reasonable and objective and if the aim is to achieve a
purpose which is legitimate under the Covenant.[29]
3.30
The question of whether different treatment under the law always amounts
to discrimination is a fundamental question in the same-sex marriage debate. The
UN HCR General Comment 18 on Article 26 of the ICCPR is clear that under
certain circumstances it does not:
[T]he Committee observes that not every differentiation of
treatment will constitute discrimination, if the criteria for such
differentiation are reasonable and objective and if the aim is to achieve a
purpose which is legitimate under the Covenant.[30]
3.31
The ICCPR's traveaux préparatoires is similarly clear when discussing
"All persons are equal before the law" in Article 7 of the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights:
The provision was intended to ensure equality, not identity,
of treatment, and would not preclude reasonable differentiations between
individuals or groups of individuals.[31]
3.32
The Human Rights Law Alliance cited General Comment 18 of Article 26 to
maintain that different treatment does not necessarily amount to discrimination
in some circumstances:
Accepting that there is no standalone right to same-sex
marriage, some allege that the right to non-discrimination and equality before
the law is the source of the right. Claims that laws which define marriage as a
man‑woman relationship infringe this right fundamentally misunderstand
the nature of the right to non-discrimination.
The right to non-discrimination and equality before the law
is a right to protection from unjust discrimination. Unjust discrimination is a
differentiation of treatment having its basis in a wholly arbitrary, subjective
or unreasonable justification.[32]
3.33
Professor Patrick Parkinson submitted:
Provisions which I propose to allow generous accommodation
for religious belief and practice would not constitute diminution of the right
to equality/non-discrimination because they are based on criteria which are
reasonable and objective, and achieve a purpose which is legitimate under the
Covenant. Therefore no question of limitation arises on the right to
equality/non-discrimination.[33]
3.34
Mark Fowler cited Joslin’s case as a statement that because
marriage is a definitional construct, questions of equality cannot arise:
[T]he United Nations Human Rights Committee held that the
concept of ‘marriage’ is a definitional construct, and by the terms of Article
23(2) of the ICCPR, included only persons of the opposite sex. Importantly, the
Committee held that the right to equality under Articles 2 or 26 of the ICCPR
was not then violated. That is to say, there is no inequality because the
definitional boundary did not enfold persons of the same sex. Such people are
equal in all respects and defining marriage as being between persons of the
opposite sex was not to render other people as unequal.[34]
3.35
The committee heard[35]
that this principle holds in the recent European jurisprudence where the ECHR
has reached similar conclusions to those of the Joslin case.[36]
Mark Fowler, citing decisions of that Court handed down in 2010, July 2014,
July 2015 and June 2016, submitted:
The ECHR has instead identified the relevant criteria for
determination of the claims of equality as being the extent to which same-sex
couples are ‘in a relevantly similar situation to a different-sex couple as
regards their need for legal recognition and protection of their relationship’.
The Court has thus held that the important claims of equality mean that same
sex relationships should be guaranteed access to equality in State recognition
and in access to protection. The content of the relevantly similar protections
included needs which are fundamental to the regulation of a relationship
between a couple in a stable and committed relationship, such as, inter alia,
the mutual rights and obligations they have towards each other, including moral
and material support, maintenance obligations and inheritance rights.[37]
3.36
In contrast, a number of submitters and witnesses contended that evolved
State practices since Joslin, in conjunction with the rights of equality
and non-discrimination (Articles 2 and 26 of the ICCPR), provide a right to
same-sex marriage.
3.37
Two of the UN HRC members in the Joslin case—who otherwise joined with
the majority position—supported the minority view that there may be
circumstances where differential treatment could amount to prohibited
discrimination under Article 26:
As to the Committee's unanimous view that it cannot find a
violation of article 26, either, in the non-recognition as marriage of the
same-sex relationships between the authors, we wish to add a few observations.
This conclusion should not be read as a general statement that
differential treatment between married couples and same-sex couples not allowed
under the law to marry would never amount to a violation of article 26. On the
contrary, the Committee's jurisprudence supports the position that such
differentiation may very well, depending on the circumstances of a concrete
case, amount to prohibited discrimination.[38]
3.38
A further view was that Article 26 of the ICCPR enshrines a 'stand-alone
right' to non-discrimination even if a measure does not engage a right
protected by the ICCPR. Accordingly, Australian Lawyers for Human Rights argued
'Australia therefore has an obligation at international law to grant equal protection
of the law to all persons in the context of marriage'.[39]
3.39
The Human Rights Law Centre's submission supported the view that the
decision in the Joslin case did not take full account of developments in human
rights principles of equality and discrimination faced by LGBTI people against
equality.[40]
3.40
Similarly, the AHRC submitted that in the Joslin case the UN HRC
narrowly interpreted Article 23 without considering its compatibility with
Articles 2 and 26:
The [UN Human Rights] Committee did not consider the
compatibility of a restrictive reading of the right to marry with the rights to
non‑discrimination and equality in articles 2 and 26 of the ICCPR. [41]
3.41
The AHRC's position is informed by Gerber et al (2014), who argued that:
Entirely absent from Joslin
v New Zealand is a consideration of how a restrictive reading of the
right to marry is compatible with the right to non-discrimination in ICCPR arts 2
and 26. In Joslin
v New Zealand, the HRC avoided answering this question by stating
that, as no right under art 23 had been found, no examination of breaches of
other articles was required.[42]
3.42
Gerber et al also discussed the criteria in General Comment 18 and
whether this was applied in the Joslin case:
In General
Comment No 18 on non-discrimination, the HRC noted that equal
treatment does not mean identical treatment; however, it went on to state that 'the
covenant is explicit' about the areas where this principle applies (for example
the segregation of juvenile offenders from adults in art 10(3)).48 The HRC also stated that differential
treatment 'will not constitute discrimination if the criteria for such differentiation
are "reasonable and objective"'. The
HRC has not applied this as a strict test, and its decision about what amounts
to reasonableness and objectivity depends largely on the circumstances.[43]
3.43
The claim that the UN HRC did not consider Articles 2 and 26 is strongly
refuted by other submitters. Professor Parkinson and Mark Fowler both submitted
in supplementary evidence that it is 'difficult to know how the Human Rights
Committee could have been clearer' when they ruled:
...the Committee cannot find that by mere refusal to provide
for marriage between homosexual couples, the State party has violated the
rights of the authors under articles 16, 17, 23, paragraphs 1 and 2, or 26 of
the Covenant.[44]
3.44
Mark Fowler similarly expressed surprise at the statement by the AHRC:
Contrary to the AHRC's assertion, the UNHCR clearly states
that it had reference to Article 26 in its reasoning. The Committee's specific
reference to Article 26 clarifies that the continuing recognition of marriage
as between a man and a woman does not amount to discrimination.
The protection against discrimination was accordingly not violated.[45]
3.45
The claim that the UN HRC did not consider Articles 2 and 26 is also
contrary to the comments of the minority members of the UN HRC themselves in
the Joslin case, wherein (as stated above at paragraph 3.37) they
referred to ‘the Committee's unanimous view that it cannot find a violation of
article 26’.
3.46
A separate question is whether there is a right to have identical
treatment under the law in relation to same-sex relationships. A number of
witnesses highlighted that Australia already has fulfilled this obligation by
legislating equality for same-sex couples in many relevant areas of law (eg:
recognition and protection of relationship, access to partner’s superannuation
etc).
3.47
Again the principles under the ICCPR Articles 2 and 26 are instructive
that there should be equality under the law for all aspects of a same-sex
relationship, and the numerous European cases have all upheld this right by
noting that equality is fulfilled in respect of legal recognition and
protection of their relationship, even if it is not identified as marriage.
Although it should be noted that in spite of there being no obligation to
provide for same-sex marriage, 13 European countries have done so.[46]
Committee view
3.48
The committee noted that evidence presented to the committee is
consistent in recognising that under current human rights instruments and
jurisprudence, there have been no decisions to date that obliges Australia to
legislate for same-sex marriage. That said, there has been no suggestion that
there are any legal impediments to doing so.
The Balancing of Rights
3.49
The key question in this, and many other inquiries, is how competing or
conflicting rights should be balanced with other rights and with the public
interest. Professor Parkinson submitted that any argument based on international
human rights must recognise that those rights are indivisible, and must be
balanced and respected:
"Balancing" does not mean that one right is crushed
under the weight of the other.[47]
3.50
Submitters and witnesses stated that, in the context of same-sex
marriage Article 26 of the ICCPR, the right to freedom from discrimination,
must be appropriately balanced with Article 18 of the ICCPR, the right to
freedom of religion[48]
Right to freedom from discrimination
3.51
The right to freedom from discrimination is a fundamental human right
protected under international human rights law and enshrined in a number of
Australian federal anti-discrimination laws and state anti-discrimination
laws. The right to non-discrimination is not absolute and can be limited when
in order to balance other rights. The Human Rights Law Centre outlined the
circumstances where such limitation is appropriate:
Given the fundamental nature of the right to equality in
upholding other human rights, limitation of this right should only occur in
where necessary, reasonable and proportionate to protect a competing
fundamental right.[49]
3.52
As with most other fundamental rights, it is subject to an assessment of
the harms of any limitation or restriction on the right. Australian Lawyers for
Human Rights explained:
...the bill presents a problem in where the appropriate balance
is between two important freedoms: the freedom of religion and the freedom from
discrimination.
To resolve this, ALHR believes the overarching principle
should be that the legislative provisions need to be an appropriate and
proportionate response to the harms being dealt with. Any restriction must have
a legitimate aim, and the means used to measure that aim must be proportionate
and necessary.[50]
3.53
The concept of comparative harm was discussed at length by Dr Greg
Walsh. Dr Walsh cited cases where, in his view, the harms suffered by the
those requesting the service, and those being potentially forced to provide it
against their conscientious beliefs is not currently balanced:
I think that in the majority of cases the harm that these
individuals—the gay couples—would suffer would be limited to the emotional harm
they suffer, the harm to their dignity and also the inconvenience of arranging
for the particular service to be provided by another service provider.
A conscientious objector will often suffer more serious harm.
If they are forced to deliver the service in contradiction to their conscience
then that will cause them to suffer grave emotional harm in many circumstances.
There may be repercussions for them in their religious community. They may be
criticised by members of their religious community. Possibly, depending upon
their religious community, it could be more serious than that.[51]
3.54
As discussed above, an individual or group receiving different treatment
before law does not automatically mean their right to be free from
discrimination has been offended. Mark Fowler submitted:
The classical and modern conception that justice requires
that ‘like cases be treated alike’ can be observed in the conclusion of both
the United Nations Human Rights Committee and the European Court of Human
Rights that the right to equality does not extend to a human right to same sex
marriage...To admit of such is not to divert at all from the political principle
which Professor Ronald Dworkin calls sovereign – ‘No government is legitimate
unless [it shows] equal concern for the fate of every person over whom it
claims dominion’. The idea that people should not be treated detrimentally in
relation to a comparable attribute is not contentious, and is a good to be
honoured within our community. Such a principle underpins the jurisprudence of
the European Court of Human Rights which has required that States afford
equality to same sex couples in respect of recognition and entitlement to
benefit. The important questions in this context are ‘what are like matters?’
and ‘what are irrelevant matters?’ in respect of the particular treatment in
question.[52]
Right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion
3.55
In its recent report on Traditional Rights and Freedoms—Encroachments
by Commonwealth Laws, the Australian Law Reform Commission characterised
religious freedom being both a positive and negative right:
Religious freedom involves positive and negative religious
liberty. Positive religious liberty involves the ‘freedom to actively manifest
one’s religion or beliefs in various spheres (public or private) and in myriad
ways (worship, teaching and so on)’. Negative
religious freedom, on the other hand, is freedom from coercion or
discrimination on the grounds of religious or non-religious belief.[53]
3.56
Article 18 of the ICCPR protects the right to freedom of thought,
conscience and religion.[54]
It provides:
1. Everyone
shall have the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion. This right
shall include freedom to have or to adopt a religion or belief of his choice,
and freedom, either individually or in community with others and in public or
private, to manifest his religion or belief in worship, observance, practice
and teaching.
2. ...
3. Freedom
to manifest one's religion or beliefs may be subject only to such limitations
as are prescribed in law and are necessary to protect public safety, order,
health, or morals or the fundamental rights and freedoms of others.
3.57
As was outlined by a number of submitters, there is a crucial
distinction between the level of protection given to religious belief
(which is absolute) as compared to the ability to manifest that
belief (which can be limited, for example, when it infringes on the rights of
others).
3.58
The right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion is not
absolute. It has two broad facets: the right to have or to adopt a
religion or belief; and the freedom to manifest one's religion or belief in
worship, observance, practice and teaching. Article 18(3) states that this
latter facet may be limited if prescribed in law and if necessary to protect,
for example, the fundamental rights and freedoms of others.
3.59
The United Nations Economic and Social Council’s Siracusa Principles on
the Limitation and Derogation Provisions in the International Covenant on Civil
and Political Rights set out the interpretive principles applicable to
limitation provisions under the ICCPR. They provide that ‘all limitation
clauses shall be interpreted strictly and in favor of the rights at issue’ and
that:
Whenever a limitation is required in the terms of the
Covenant to be "necessary," this term implies that the limitation:
- is based on one of the
grounds justifying limitations recognized by the relevant article of the
Covenant,
- responds to a pressing public or
social need,
- pursues a legitimate aim,
and
- is proportionate to that aim.’
They also state that ‘in applying a limitation, a state shall
use no more restrictive means than are required'.[55]
3.60
The United Nations Human Rights Committee (UN HRC), which monitors
implementation of the ICCPR, explained:
...States parties should proceed from the need to protect the
rights guaranteed under the Covenant, including the right to equality and non‑discrimination
on all grounds specified in articles 2, 3 and 26. Limitations imposed must be
established by law and must not be applied in a manner that would vitiate the
rights guaranteed in article 18. The Committee observes that paragraph 3
of article 18 is to be strictly interpreted: restrictions are not allowed on grounds
not specified there, even if they would be allowed as restrictions to other
rights protected in the Covenant, such as national security.[56]
3.61
The Human Rights Law Centre outlines how the limitations in Article
18(3) are required due to the unique nature of the right to freedom of
religion:
...the limitations contained in Article 18 of the ICCPR
exercise an important corrective function due to the potential for far-reaching
freedom of religion to lead to suppression not merely of freedom of religion of
others but to other rights as well. This is because of the inherently
controversial nature of freedom of religion – the fact that most religious
faiths believe their faith to represent the ‘absolute truth’ and thus reject
the faiths of others.[57]
3.62
A number of submissions outlined methodology and examples for the
balancing of the two rights and examples from international jurisprudence of
where the right to freedom of religion and the right to freedom from
discrimination intersects. A key feature of where the dividing line should be
struck, according to a number of submitters, is determined in reference to the
closeness of the particular conduct to the observance, worship and practice of
religion.
Religion as an Exemption
3.63
In response to the Terms of Reference, a large number of submitters and
witnesses argued that the Exposure Draft Bill does not sufficiently protect the
right to freedom of conscience and religion. For some, this is
demonstrated by the treating this right as an exemption, thereby failing to
recognise its status as a fundamental right. For example, the Anglican Church
Diocese of Sydney submitted:
Instead of categorising religious freedom as an
"exemption" to human rights, our legislative framework needs to
recognise that Article 18 of the ICCPR recognises a right to
freedom of thought, conscience and religion, and that this right needs to be
balanced against other rights also recognised in ICCPR, such as Article 26.[58]
3.64
A number of submitters and witnesses argued that Australian law and the
Exposure Draft Bill, does not sufficiently protect the right to freedom of
conscience and religion. For some, there was a specific objection to
dealing with freedom of religion by way of enacting exemption, and thereby
failing to recognise its status as a fundamental right.
3.65
As noted in Chapter 1, the term exemption is not used in the Exposure
Draft, but has developed as shorthand to describe the protection of religious
organisations and individuals from claims under anti-discrimination law, which
is the legal effect of key clauses in the Exposure Draft.
3.66
Associate Professor Neil Foster commented that anti-discrimination law
recognises the need to protect religious freedom in laws that deal with
differing social views on moral issues about sexual behaviour and orientation.
Similar to that law, he suggested:
Rather than describing such provisions as
"exemptions", with all the overtones of narrowness of reading that
this implies, the better view is that these are best seen as "balancing
clauses", which allow the balancing of important rights not to be subject
to unjust discrimination, with the fundamental religious convictions of many
persons and bodies in the community.[59]
3.67
Marriage Alliance also objected to how the protections for religious
freedom were framed:
We submit that religious freedom is a fundamental human
right, that framing a debate in terms of exemptions misunderstands this fact... [60]
3.68
There was common ground between many groups on the need for positive
protection for religious freedom. The Human Rights Law Centre and other
organisations in support of same sex marriage recognised the need for
Australian law to positively protect religious freedom.
Religious freedom should be protected in law. Indeed we are
on record in a number of inquiries supporting the addition of religious belief
to protections under federal anti-discrimination law.[61]
A right to refuse on religious grounds, but only for same-sex marriages
3.69
As discussed in Chapter 2 the provision that allows religious ministers
to refuse to solemnise a same-sex marriage is broadly supported. However while
the freedom of religion has long been balanced with freedom from
discrimination, the proposed amendment to the Marriage Act only exempts
religious ministers from marrying same-sex couples. The bill singles out same-sex
couples while not making mention of divorced, inter-faith, non-religious or
couples of a different religion (all of who can be excluded from a religious
wedding due to certain religions prerequisites for marriage).
3.70
Some witnesses submitted that the wording of the exemption may raise an
inconsistency with Article 7 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights,
which states that '[a]ll are equal before the law and are entitled without any
discrimination to equal protection of the law',. The Committee notes however
that the UDHR is not a treaty and does not create binding obligations on States.
The UDHR has however given rise to applicable rights contained in the ICCPR and
that the jurisprudence around those rights has been developed over time as outlined
in this Report.
3.71
Article 18 of the Universal Declaration of Human Right outlines the
right to 'to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship and
observance'.[62]
The freedom to publically observe ones religion is also maintained in Article
18(1) of the ICCPR, 'freedom, either individually or in community with others
and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in worship,
observance, practice and teaching.'[63]
3.72
However, the freedom of religion must be considered in conjunction with Article
26 of the ICCPR:
All persons are equal before the law and are entitled without
any discrimination to the equal protection of the law. In this respect, the law
shall prohibit any discrimination and guarantee to all persons equal and
effective protection against discrimination on any ground such as race, colour,
sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin,
property, birth or other status.[64]
3.73
As highlighted in para 3.52, when Article 26 conflicts with Article 18,
there needs to be a way to ensure that harms are proportionate.
3.74
Professor Patrick Parkinson and Mark Fowler noting that the religious
freedom protection under Article 18 of the ICCPR can only be limited by other
fundamental rights observed that the absence of a right to same sex marriage in
international law has consequences for the ability to limit religious freedoms:
Since the right to marry a person of the same gender is not
required by the ICCPR, and the principle of non-discrimination in Article 26
can be satisfied by providing equal rights other than the right to marry, the
right to maintain religious beliefs and practices in relation to religious
understandings of marriage is not limited by any right of a person to marry
another person of the same gender.[65]
3.75
Mark Fowler submitted:
There is not an obligation for a state to impose that [same
sex marriage], and they therefore conclude, both in the European context and
the UN context, that the right to discrimination is not enlivened. That leads
us to ask: where is the limiting right on religious freedom under article 18,
and under article 9 of the European convention?[66]
Goods and services
3.76
Under the proposed section 47B, a religious body or religious
organisation may refuse to make a facility available or may refuse to provide
goods and services if the marriage is not the union of a man and a woman; and
the refusal confirms to the doctrines tenets or beliefs of the religion, body
or organisation or would injure the religious susceptibilities of adherents of
the religion.
3.77
A number of submitters pointed to international human rights law
jurisprudence providing guidance on the question of whether the provision of
goods and services in a secular market place would attraction protection as the
‘manifestation of religious belief’. In order to attract protection, there must
be a close and direct nexus between the act and the underlying belief. For
example, the Human Rights Law Centre submitted that:
Whether discrimination should be permitted requires careful
assessment on a base by case basis. For example, it would be reasonable for a
church hall used by a congregation for activities related to the practice and
observance of their religion to not be made available to same-sex couples for
their wedding (assuming the doctrines of that particular faith did not support
same-sex marriage). It would be an entirely different proposition if a
religious owned (but not branded) commercial convention centre or similar venue
was to advertise its services generally to the market place and then seek to
cancel a booking from a couple upon finding out that the couple were off the
same sex.[67]
3.78
However, it should be noted that the Australian Parliament has
previously determined the ability of religious organisations to discriminate in
the provision of goods and services (including hiring of facilities for
weddings or marriage related services such as catering) to discriminate where
this discrimination would accord with the doctrines, tenets or beliefs of their
religious order or would be necessary to avoid injury to the susceptibilities
of adherents to their religion.[68]
The amendments to the Sex Discrimination Act 1984 (Cth) that enshrined
this position were passed with support from the Labor Government and Coalition
Opposition led by Tony Abbott.
3.79
Article 1 (2) of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights provides the right to 'freely dispose of their natural wealth
and resources without prejudice to any obligations arising out of international
economic co-operation, based upon the principle of mutual benefit''. Some
witnesses argued that the curtailing of a person's access to goods and services
due to their sexual preferences would be inconsistent with this freedom in
addition to the freedom of legal equality.
3.80
The committee notes however that as Article 1(2) protects the rights of
people to dispose of their resources as they see fit, it would also support
services suppliers refusing to supply services to people they do not wish to do
so. In its historical context, the clause was a statement of sovereign states
ability to control their own resources. The UNHRC in its Gen Comment 12
clarifies:
Paragraph 2 affirms a particular aspect of the economic
content of the right of selfdetermination, namely the right of peoples, for
their own ends, freely to “dispose of their natural wealth and resources
without prejudice to any obligations arising out of international economic
cooperation, based upon the principle of mutual benefit, and international law.
In no case may a people be deprived of its own means of subsistence”. This
right entails corresponding duties for all States and the international
community. States should indicate any factors or difficulties which prevent the
free disposal of their natural wealth and resources contrary to the provisions
of this paragraph and to what extent that affects the enjoyment of other rights
set forth in the Covenant.[69]
3.81
For this reason, the SDA was pointed to by a number of submitters
as an appropriate standard to be adopted in relation to this reform. For
example, the Law Council submitted that the protections afforded to religious
bodies and organisations in section 37 of the Sex Discrimination Act are
sufficient to protect religious freedom, and render the proposed section 47B
unnecessary. Moreover, they are also of the view that in the absence of a
definition for religious bodies and organisations, the inclusion of this clause
would cause 'unnecessary complexity and uncertainty'.[70]
A number of other submitters with legal and human rights expertise shared this
position.[71]
3.82
Equal Voices were also about the types of organisations that would be
covered, and also what types of goods and services:
Such a broad scope may include not only organisations which
have the express purpose of advancing religious practice, such as churches, but
those operating to provide services to the public, services which the public
should feel reasonably entitled to access.
...
‘Purposes reasonably incidental to’ is not defined in the
Exposure Draft. The common dictionary definition of ‘incidental to’ is ‘liable
to happen as a consequence of’. The inclusion of these ‘incidental purposes’
gives vast scope for the refusal of basic goods and services.[72]
3.83
In contrast, the Wilberforce Foundation were of the view that the
inclusion of section 47B was a legitimate protection for religious organisations:
...when it is considered that facilities like church halls
etc are built and maintained by the money, time and labour of the adherents of
the faith. It would be a violation of conscience to coerce such premises to be
used or a purpose contrary to the doctrines of the faith, the maintenance and
advancement of which has motivated people to help with the creation of such
facilities. Similar reasons support the freedom extending to the provision of
goods and services. They are provided to further the faith and adherents should
not be compelled to provide those good or services contrary to the faith.[73]
3.84
Equal Opportunity Tasmania point out that the freedom to refuse to
provide facilities, or goods and services 'gives rise to extremely complex
legal and religious questions'. Their submission cited the Cobaw v Christian
youth Camps case in Victoria which ruled on the limitations of an
organisation to refuse to provide services on religious grounds:
This is a matter given significant attention in Cobaw v
Christian Youth Camps in which Hampel J turned her mind to whether the
services provided by the Christian Brethren in camping and conference
facilities could be properly construed as services avowedly religious in
character or whether their purpose was primarily secular or commercial.
In her reasoning, Hampel J examined issues regarding the
nature of the service provided by the organisation and whether there was a
tangible or explicit religious content associated with the services provided.
In the case of Christian Youth Camps, Her Honour concluded that the purposes of
the organisation were not ‘directly and immediately religious’ and that
although there was a connection with a church or denomination this was not
sufficient for the Christian Youth Camps to claim the benefit of exception from
liability for conduct that was otherwise discriminatory. [74]
3.85
This view was partially supported by the Anglican Church Diocese of
Sydney who agreed that only those services 'intrinsic' to the ceremony who
should be protected should they wish not to participate in a same-sex wedding:
It is where the personal services are on site or the artistic
contribution is intrinsic to the wedding itself. The closer that nexus the more
important it is to give people the option to not be forced to participate against
their conscience.[75]
3.86
Bishop Comensoli expanded on this definition by suggesting three words
to describe applicable goods or services:
...what is intrinsic to, directly associated with and
intimately involved. The taxi driver driving somebody to a wedding? No.[76]
3.87
Australians For Equality and Australian Marriage Equality raised the
potential for significant detriment or disadvantage for same-sex couples,
depending on the definition given to religious body or organisation. It would
be undesirable, for example, if a service provider or venue with no religious
presence or ‘branding’ was to avail themselves of an exemption. This would have
the potential to cause distress, embarrassment and disadvantage for same-sex
couples that might have booked or purchased facilities or services not
realising that the entity was religious in origin.[77]
3.88
The committee heard of concerns on whether the current balance between
anti-discrimination law and the freedom to exercise other rights is
appropriate. Attention was drawn to cases such as Ashers Bakery in Northern
Ireland[78]
where a small business was ruled to have discriminated on the basis of a
protected attribute. The ruling illustrates that in some cases
anti-discrimination law can be exercised to the detriment of other fundamental rights.
Committee view
3.89
The committee notes that Commonwealth law already allows organisations
established for religious purposes to discriminate in the delivery of goods and
services, including marriage related services and the hiring of facilities,
where this discrimination accords with religious doctrine, tenets or beliefs or
is necessary to avoid injury to the susceptibilities of adherents to their
religion. However the committee also notes that Australia's obligations under
international human rights law apply to individuals as well as groups.
Individuals providing facilities,
goods and services
3.90
Several submitters and witnesses referred to international and domestic
experience where individuals have been sued for refusing to provide
facilities, goods and/or services for a same-sex marriage.[79]
3.91
A number of participants noted that paragraph 37(1)(d) of the Sex
Discrimination Act exempts only religious bodies from the protections against
discrimination contained in Divisions 1 and 2 of Part II of the Sex Discrimination
Act:
(d) any other act or practice of a body established for
religious purposes, being an act or practice that conforms to the doctrines,
tenets or beliefs of that religion or is necessary to avoid injury to the
religious susceptibilities of adherents of that religion.
3.92
The Attorney-General's Department and the Australian Human Rights
Commission pointed out that proposed new section 47B also applies only to
religious bodies, meaning that there is no protection in Australian law for
individuals who might not wish to provide commercial goods and services for
same-sex weddings.[80]
3.93
Laura Sweeney, Specialist LGBTI Adviser from the Australian Human
Rights Commission, said:
The exemption as proposed in the exposure draft is...limited to...bodies
established for religious purposes, religious bodies or religious organisations
so there is no sense in which, at least on our understanding without the
explanatory memorandum, the proposed exemption in the exposure draft would be [broadened]
to a baker, for example.[81]
3.94
The Human Rights Commissioner expressed the need for caution before
considering the extension of these exemptions to individuals providing a
commercial service:
...Australian law for many years has not allowed you to
undertake what is unlawful discrimination. The current exposure draft bill
reflects that, and we support that. If what you are saying is that there may be
new areas that are not currently set out in the exposure draft bill where
unlawful discrimination would no longer be unlawful, we would need to look at
those very carefully and we would be very, very wary of them.[82]
3.95
Professor Nicholas Aroney and Dr Joel Harrison took a contrary view:
While religious bodies and religious organisations are
protected in the Draft Bill in relation to the making available of facilities
and the provision of goods and services, this protection does not extend to
individuals. There is no reason in principle why the protection should be
limited in this way. Individuals should enjoy the same protections as religious
bodies and organisations in this respect. The only requirement should be that a
decision not to make facilities available or to refuse to provide goods and
services is sincerely motivated by the religious beliefs or convictions of the
individual or individuals involved. ...
there is a real risk that organisations formed for purposes
that are not primarily religious, but are still deeply motivated by religious
beliefs or convictions, will not be protected. Just because a corporation is
formed, for example, for the purpose of providing welfare or educational
services, or even for making a commercial profit, does not necessarily mean
that its actions cannot be sincerely motivated by religious beliefs or
convictions. The recent Hobby Lobby case in the United States illustrates how
this can be the case...
Sincerely motivated decisions by individuals and groups to
act or not act in certain ways do not necessarily cease to be acts of religious
conscience simply because they occur in a commercial setting. As the High Court
of Australia recognised in Commissioner of Taxation v Word Investments (2008)
236 CLR 204, extensive engagement in commercial activities and charitable
status on religious grounds are not mutually exclusive categories.[83]
3.96
The Committee notes that a number of submissions have suggested how this
purpose could be achieved with minor amendments to the Exposure Draft.[84]
Committee view
3.97
The vast majority of contributors supported the right for religious
ministers to refuse to solemnise a same-sex marriage. However there were
questions why this applies only to same-sex marriages and not other aspects of
religious doctrine, tenets or belief. Submitters suggested that the explicit
insertion for same-sex marriages effectively limits the current freedom for
religious ministers not to solemnise any marriage on religious grounds should
they wish to do so. While noting the Attorney General's Department's reasoning
about the risks of the exemption being applied to other protected attributes
under anti-discrimination law, perhaps a better option should be found without
limiting the freedom of religious ministers and singling out same-sex couples.
3.98
While the evidence received accepts that existing law allows religious
organisations to discriminate against same-sex couples in the provision of
goods and services, the terms religious body or religious organisation need to
be clearly defined. The connection between the organisation and the goods and
services being provided may need to be articulated to determine if commercial
companies owned by religious organisations are exempt from providing services.
3.99
The ICCPR, the traveaux préparatoires, the Siracusa Principles and
General Comment 18 together require that there are circumstances where broader
considerations can be taken into account. Whether this principle could be
applied to achieve an appropriate balance of rights is worthy of further
consideration.
3.100
Some committee members were of the view that Australian discrimination
law already resolves questions of competing rights in the context of commercial
goods and services and these laws have operated without significant controversy
for a number of years.
A right to refuse on the grounds of a conscientious belief
3.101
Section 47A of the Exposure Draft Bill introduces the right of
celebrants to refuse to solemnise a same-sex marriage based on 'conscientious
or religious belief'. Under the current Marriage Act, celebrants do not appear
to have the right to refuse to marry a person based on such beliefs. Although
there was some express support for proposed new subsection 47A(1) (see chapter
two), some submitters argued that proposed new paragraph 47A(1)(b) is too
broad. Submitters expressed concern that this would lead to discrimination,
contrary to Article 26 of the ICCPR, and undermined established principles of
Australian anti-discrimination law.
3.102
In General Comment 22 on Article 18, the UN HRC states that the
freedom to manifest religion or conscientious belief may be exercised:
..."either individually or in community with others and in
public or private". The freedom to manifest religion or belief in worship,
observance, practice and teaching encompasses a broad range of acts. The
concept of worship extends to ritual and ceremonial acts giving direct
expression to belief, as well as various practices integral to such acts,
including the building of places of worship, the use of ritual formulae and
objects, the display of symbols, and the observance of holidays and days
of rest.[85]
3.103
The Human Rights Law Centre agreed that religious freedom is both individual
and collective in nature, but that it must be connected to the religion:
...an individual right, but the right is based on religious
belief that is linked back to a particular religious order or religious
denomination.[86]
3.104
Contributors agreed that this was a complex area of law to expand into. The
Anti-discrimination Board of New South Wales described the problem of expanding
the freedom to manifest a belief beyond religion:
Where you have established doctrine of
a church or tenets of belief you can point to that and say: 'This is what the
cannon law says,' or 'This is what the doctrines, as pronounced, guide us
towards how we live our lives.' Where you talk about individual or
conscientious belief that becomes an individual exercise. People's individual
beliefs can change. They can be informed by events. They can be informed by
debate. So it will become an individual view at a particular time, in a
particular set of circumstances.[87]
3.105
The Castan Centre for Human Rights Law submitted that domestic or
international law provides little guidance as to the meaning of the term
'conscientious belief':
As far as we can tell, the term is unique...With no discourse
in international or domestic law to look to for an understanding of the parameters,
this term creates uncertainty and potential to be widely construed. This could
have the effect of unjustly increasing the instances of discrimination against
LGBTIQ couples.[88]
3.106
The Victorian Government pointed out that if civil celebrants were able
to refuse to solemnise a same-sex marriage, Australia would be unique amongst
comparable countries:
It is notable that in the comparable jurisdictions of New
Zealand, the United Kingdom and Canada, civic marriage celebrants do not have
the ability to refuse to solemnise marriages that are not between a man and a
woman.[89]
3.107
Others noted that the proposed ground for exemption would be in excess
of the grounds provided for in paragraph 37(1)(d) of the Sex Discrimination Act,
as well as state and territory equal opportunity and anti-discrimination laws.
For example, the AHRC submitted:
Permitting a celebrant to discriminate on the basis of
conscience, as distinct from their religious beliefs, exceeds the exemptions
contained in the Sex Discrimination Act and all state and territory
anti-discrimination and equal opportunity laws, which include exemptions for
discrimination on the basis of the doctrines, tenets or beliefs of a religion
or to avoid injury to the religious susceptibilities of adherents of the
religion, but not on the basis of 'conscientious belief'.[90]
3.108
Article 18 protects individual conscience separate from religious
conviction. General Comment 22 provides:
The Committee draws the attention of States parties to the
fact that the freedom of thought and the freedom of conscience are protected
equally with the freedom of religion and belief.[91]
3.109
Mark Fowler drew the Committee’s attention to the Siracusa Principles,
which state that 'in applying a limitation, a state shall use no more
restrictive means than are required'. He argued that in the case of civil
celebrants a proportionate treatment that would balance their rights against
countervailing rights would take into account means by which both rights can be
preserved. He asked whether it might be ‘possible to have on the register a
demarcation of those persons who are willing to offer services to same-sex
attracted persons in the context of marriage celebration’ as a means to acquit
Australia’s obligations to undertake such a balancing exercise.[92]
3.110
The Australian Human Rights Centre were wary of the implications of
allowing civil celebrants the right to refuse to solemnise a same-sex marriage:
The idea that a personal moral view could be used to treat
someone unfairly because of a particular attribute strikes at the very heart of
the rationale for our discrimination laws to begin with, which is all about
ensuring equal treatment regardless of particular personal attributes.
Introducing a justification for discrimination on the basis of a personal moral
view is giving a blank cheque to discriminate.[93]
Celebrants as public servants
3.111
The role of celebrants as providers of a public service was also raised
by numerous submitters. As those administering civil marriage under civil law,
it was thought by many submitters that it would be inappropriate to allow civil
celebrants to refuse to perform a same-sex marriage once it was provided for
under civil law.
3.112
In line with the view that freedom of thought, conscience and religion
applies equally to individuals as well as organisations, Professor Neil Foster
was supportive of celebrants having protection in the Bill, and also suggested
a protection for other public servants:
I...support the conscientious refusal clause for private
celebrants. Private celebrants, as I have said previously, do not lose their
rights of religious freedom when they start their business...
I also, though, think that the bill does not go far enough...I
think protection is needed for Public Service registry offices. I think
rostering arrangements and other things can be made so that people will not be
inconvenienced if a right is given to public service registry officers.[94]
3.113
Professor Nicholas Aroney and Dr Joel Harrison supported this view:
While ministers of religion and marriage celebrants are
protected in the Draft Bill, marriage registry officials, who are authorised to
solemnise marriages under s 39 of the Marriage Act, are not protected.
Protecting registry officials in addition to ministers of religion and marriage
celebrants is necessary to meet the kinds of problems that arose, for example,
in the Ladele case in the United Kingdom and the Davis case in the United
States. This protection should be available provided there is a reasonably
available alternative in the circumstances of any particular case.
3.114
In contrast, Dr Dane who was appearing with Just.Equal said that the
results of the survey she carried out the view of the majority of respondents
was:
...if you are working as a public servant, you need to fulfil
that role. If you do not want to do that, then you need to find some other form
of employment.[95]
3.115
Similarly, the Uniting Church LGBTIQ Network submitted that they did not
support protection for anyone other than a religious minister:
[W]e do not support extending exemptions beyond religious officiants.
The role of civil celebrants provides a particular alternative to religious
marriage. There is no justification, in terms of religious freedom, to allow
specific discrimination against a particular group of Australian citizens.[96]
3.116
The AHRC and many others also contributed on this point:
Marriage under the Marriage Act is not inherently religious
in nature; it is a civil process that confers a legal status on the parties to
it. In performing marriages, marriage celebrants are solely performing the role
of the state in solemnising marriages. [97]
3.117
A related aspect raised by submitters is whether religious ministers can
act in accordance with their own belief, which may contrast with the tenets and
doctrines of their religious denomination. As noted by the Wilberforce
Foundation, individual conscience might not always conform to a particular
religion:
As the Canadian Supreme Court has recognized an individual's
right to religious freedom does not necessitate an inquiry into whether their "beliefs
are objectively recognized as valid by other members of the same religion, nor
is such as inquiry appropriate for courts to make". In an Australian
context, Christian Youth Camps and Anor v Cobaw Community Health Services
Ltd and Ors demonstrates the accuracy of the Canadian Supreme Court's
observation as courts are not well equipped to decide on doctrines which are
part of a religion's beliefs or not, particularly where, in some cases,
denominations have not spelled out their beliefs.[98]
3.118
This is somewhat addressed in General Comment 22 on Article 18 the UN
HRC discusses the fact that every individual person has the right to that
freedom of conscience and the manifestation of that, which goes beyond formalised
religions:
The terms "belief" and "religion" are to
be broadly construed. Article 18 is not limited in its application to
traditional religions or to religions and beliefs with institutional
characteristics or practices analogous to those of traditional religions. The
Committee therefore views with concern any tendency to discriminate against any
religion or belief for any reason, including the fact that they are newly
established, or represent religious minorities that may be the subject of
hostility on the part of a predominant religious community.[99]
Committee view
3.119
The evidence presented was generally in favour of the right for
ministers to refuse to solemnise a marriage on religious grounds. However
extending this right to civil celebrants on religious grounds proved more controversial.
Extending the right to either ministers of religion or civil celebrants to
conscientious grounds met with even stronger resistance from submitters, given
the lack of precedent under Australian law and the risks presented.
3.120
The committee is guided by the limited usage of conscientious belief in
Australian law today and notes that to allow conscientious belief to be used to
allow discrimination against a class of persons would be unprecedented under
Australian law. The Committee would be disinclined to disturb decades of
anti-discrimination law and practice in Australia. Overall, the weight of
evidence received in this inquiry suggests there are philosophical questions
that go to the very definition of religion, marriage, and a democratic society
that require full consideration.
3.121
In human rights law, the freedom to thought or conscience, or to have a
religion or belief are protected unconditionally, but the manifestation of
religion or belief are subject to some limitations under the ICCPR. Extending protections
in the context of same-sex marriage on conscientious grounds introduces the
complex question of whether the manifestation of a non-religious conscientious
belief has the same level of protection as religious belief under international
human rights law in this specific area.
3.122
General Comment 22 makes the specific point that equal protection is
afforded to conscience, and as such any attempt to differentiate on the rights
of an individual based on conscience vs religion may be contested (noting that
as far as the committee is aware, this has been considered in the courts, to
date. However the weight of evidence received in this inquiry suggests there
are schools of thought that go to the very definition of religion, marriage,
and a democratic society that require full consideration.
A broader protection of the right to freedom
of conscience and religion
3.123
Several submitters and witnesses referred to experience internationally
and in Australia, where the same-sex marriage debate and/or the legalisation of
same-sex marriage has led to adverse action against individuals who hold and
manifest the religious or conscientious belief that marriage is between a man
and a woman.[100]
3.124
The cases cited most often involved individuals employed by the State
and/or small businesses in the wedding industry. Associate Professor Foster
submitted:
Many of the cases overseas have involved businesses who were
perfectly happy to serve gay customers generally. But when it comes to a
specific ceremony, the sole aim of which is to celebrate and rejoice over the
entry into a long-lasting same sex relationship, which is contrary to the moral
teaching of most mainstream religious groups: then these people have simply
wanted to be able to politely decline to be dragooned into providing their
support.[101]
3.125
Associate Professor Foster submitted that such experience has resulted
in a perceived threat to freedom of speech:
...especially so since litigation against the Roman Catholic
Archbishop of Hobart, claiming that material he had issued to Roman Catholic
schools on the traditional Roman Catholic views on sexual behaviour, had caused
"offence" under the very broadly worded s 17 of the Anti-Discrimination
Act 1998 (Tas). Perhaps with some justification, there are concerns that if
this litigation (which was approved to continue by a Tasmanian tribunal, before
eventually being abandoned) went so far when the view being put was consistent
with current Australian law, then there would be even more pressure to be
silent following a change of the law to allow same sex marriage.[102]
3.126
The Apostolic Church of Australia agreed:
The current freedoms we possess will be stifled and the
consequences for religious freedom will be serious, as they have been for those
overseas that have adopted similar suggestions...ministers will have less freedom
when it comes to acting as a minister should this suggestion be passed.[103]
3.127
Mr Christopher Brohier from the Wilberforce Foundation said:
...the parliament cannot ignore that there are lots and lots of
Australians who are sincerely opposed to same-sex marriage...Those people should
not be labelled as illegal discriminators...Their religious conscientious
identity is just as much a part of their identity as a person who identifies as
a same‑sex attracted individual.[104]
Protection against discrimination
on the basis of religious belief
3.128
Some submitters and witnesses contended that, in general, Australia
needs better protection of the right to freedom of conscience and religion. For
example, the Institute for Civil Society submitted that, unlike other
countries, there is no statutory right to religious freedom:
We are really pressing a right not to be discriminated
against for holding a view in favour of traditional marriage...there is no
statutory protection against discrimination on the ground of religion in
federal law, NSW law and very little in South Australian law. Whereas
discrimination on the grounds of sexual orientation is prohibited in all
Australian jurisdictions. Thus there is a significantly greater coverage of
discrimination law protection of sexual orientation than of religious belief
and activity.[105]
3.129
The Human Rights Law Centre were also strongly supportive about ensuring
that religious freedom should be better protected in law:
We are also very happy for the provision around religious
freedom to be framed in a positive way. Religious freedom should be protected
in law. Indeed, we are on record in a number of inquiries supporting the
addition of religious belief to protections under federal anti-discrimination
law.[106]
3.130
The Human Rights Commissioner, Ed Santow, told the committee that
protection for freedom of religion could 'logically' be included in
consolidated anti-discrimination law. In
2012, the Australian Government had considered such a reform, releasing an
exposure draft of the Human Rights and Anti-Discrimination Bill 2012.[107] The Bill was referred to the
Senate Legal and Constitutional Affairs Legislation Committee for examination.[108] However, after that committee's
report was tabled, the Australian Government decided not to proceed with
the legislative consolidation at that time.[109]
3.131
In the absence of a consolidated anti-discrimination law, the Human
Rights Commissioner said:
...you could have a stand-alone statute that specifically dealt
with freedom of religion or you could expand the Racial Discrimination Act.
There are, of course...some real dangers in treating race and religion as if they
were one and the same thing...But if the statute itself were broadened in its
scope appropriately then that may be a similarly appropriate way of dealing
with that issue.[110]
3.132
The Australian Human Rights Commission agreed that there should be a
specific protection in federal law on the basis of religious belief:
This would be the most orthodox approach to address the
problem identified—namely, the risk of discrimination or adverse action
against a person because of their religious belief. It would conform with the
way that other 'protected attributes'—such as race, disability, sex and age—are
given legal protection. It would also be consistent with the approach taken to
discrimination on the basis of religious belief in most Australian states and
territories...In addition, this approach would further protect the right to
freedom of religion in article 18 of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (ICCPR), and freedom from religious discrimination in article
26 of the ICCPR, by strengthening existing federal protections against
discrimination on the basis of religion.[111]
The United Kingdom approach
3.133
Some submitters specifically noted that, in the United Kingdom, free
speech protections accompanied the introduction of same-sex marriage.[112]
In their view, the Australian Parliament should do likewise. For example,
Associate Professor Foster proposed the following provision:
For the avoidance of doubt, for the purposes of any law of
the Commonwealth, a State or a Territory dealing with vilification or the
causing of offence on the grounds of sexual orientation, any discussion or
criticism of marriage which concerns the sex of the parties to marriage shall
not be taken for that reason alone to be offensive, threatening, or intended to
stir up or incite hatred, serious contempt for, or severe ridicule of, a person
or group of persons on those grounds.[113]
3.134
The Institute for Civil Society also suggested looking to the
protections introduced in the United Kingdom.[114]
Broad anti-detriment provision
3.135
The Institute of Civil Society stated that the Exposure Draft Bill does
not adequately protect freedom of religion and freedom of conscience within the
context of same-sex marriage, and as a response recommended the introduction of
further protections:
...we propose the introduction of a broad, federal
anti-detriment provision, which would prohibit both governments and private
sector organisations from acting detrimentally towards a person or an
organisation simply because they hold or express a view that marriage is
between a man and a woman, or who are perhaps associated with a group that
holds that view.[115]
3.136
The Institute of Civil Society argued that religious belief and activity
are not protected attributes in all jurisdictions (such as the Commonwealth,
New South Wales and South Australia), compared to anti-discrimination
protections on the ground of sexual orientation: 'there
is a significantly greater coverage of discrimination law protection of sexual
orientation than of religious belief and activity'.[116]
3.137
Dr Sharon Rodrick from the Institute of Civil Society explained that,
under its proposal, religious beliefs would be treated as a protected attribute:
...it would be used to protect the rights of people not to be
discriminated against because of their religious beliefs. It would give effect
to freedom of religion and freedom of conscience, which are both stand-alone
human rights recognised in the ICCPR. It would also give effect to the right of
people not to be discriminated against on the basis of religion, under article
26 of the ICCPR. Discrimination cuts both ways. Just as there is a right not to
be discriminated against because of your sex or sexual orientation, so there
is an equivalent right not to be discriminated against because of your
religion.[117]
3.138
The Anglican Church Diocese of Sydney considered that a broad anti‑detriment
provision would provide better protection for religious freedom, than as
proposed in the Exposure Draft Bill. However, in its view, such a provision
ought to go further:
It only protects the right to non‑discrimination on the
basis of one's view about marriage, but does not provide any positive
protection for Religious Freedom rights which might be overturned should the
legal definition of marriage be changed.[118]
3.139
Both the Australian Human Rights Commission and the Institute of Civil
Society noted that any anti-detriment provision would need to be carefully
drafted, to properly set out its intended scope and operation.[119]
3.140
Mark Fowler raised another possible detriment to religious charities
arising from the Bill. Citing the common law doctrine that a charity's purposes
must not be contrary to public policy and authority from the United States, New
Zealand, Canada and England and Wales he argued for amendments to the Charities
Act 2013 (Cth) to ensure religious charities with a traditional view of
marriage retain their charitable status.[120]
Committee view
Anti-discrimination law reform
3.141
The committee is cognisant of previous attempts to reform federal
anti-discrimination law. Such reforms are unavoidably complex, requiring expert
consideration of international human rights obligations and federal, state and
territory laws, as well as relevant jurisprudence. The committee notes that the
Australian Government has previously considered and attempted to progress such
a reform and, indeed, has already protected individuals from discrimination in
employment on the basis of religious belief or political belief in the Fair
Work Act. In the committee's view, the arguments for protecting religious
freedom in Australia support reconsideration of these matters.
3.142
Overall the evidence supports the need for current protections for
religious freedom to be enhanced. This would most appropriately be achieved
through the inclusion of 'religious belief' in federal anti-discrimination law.
The idea of a 'no detriment' clause was not canvassed extensively in this
inquiry given that it is not proposed by the Exposure Draft. Should a parliament
decide to legislate in this area, further examination of the potential form and
consequences of such a clause is required before such a concept could be
recommended by the Committee.
Senator David Fawcett
Liberal Party of Australia, SA
Navigation: Previous Page | Contents | Next Page